1. 44845.834613
    There are many reasons for objecting to quantifying the ‘proof beyond reasonable doubt’ standard of criminal law as a percentage probability. They are divided into ethical and policy reasons, on the one hand, and reasons arising from the nature of logical probabilities, on the other. It is argued that these reasons are substantial and suggest that the criminal standard of proof should not be given a precise number. But those reasons do not rule out a minimal imprecise number. ‘Well above 80%’ is suggested as a standard, implying that any attempt by a prosecutor or jury to take the ‘proof beyond reasonable doubt’ standard to be 80% or less should be ruled out as a matter of law.
    Found 12 hours, 27 minutes ago on James Franklin's site
  2. 77872.834683
    The aim of the paper is to understand what is involved in the claim that a mental state in general and love in particular, is based on reasons. Love, like many other mental states, can be evaluated in various ways: it can be considered appropriate, deserved, enriching, perverse, destructive etc. but this does not mean that love is based on reasons. In this paper I present and defend a test that a mental state has to satisfy if it is to count as based on reasons. This test will be used to construct a new argument in favour of Frankfurt's position that love is not based on reasons.
    Found 21 hours, 37 minutes ago on PhilPapers
  3. 88985.834751
    After a sketch of the optimism and high aspirations of History and Philosophy of Science when I first joined the field in the mid 1960s, I go on to describe the disastrous impact of "the strong programme" and social constructivism in history and sociology of science. Despite Alan Sokal's brilliant spoof article, and the "science wars" that flared up partly as a result, the whole field of Science and Technology Studies (STS) is still adversely affected by social constructivist ideas. I then go on to spell out how in my view STS ought to develop. It is, to begin with, vitally important to recognize the profoundly problematic character of the aims of science. There are substantial, influential and highly problematic metaphysical, value and political assumptions built into these aims. Once this is appreciated, it becomes clear that we need a new kind of science which subjects problematic aims - problematic assumptions inherent in these aims - to sustained imaginative and critical scrutiny as an integral part of science itself. This needs to be done in an attempt to improve the aims and methods of science as science proceeds. The upshot is that science, STS, and the relationship between the two, are all transformed. STS becomes an integral part of science itself. And becomes a part of an urgently needed campaign to transform universities so that they become devoted to helping humanity create a wiser world.
    Found 1 day ago on PhilSci Archive
  4. 96941.834787
    The religious phenomenon is a complex one in many respects. In recent years an increasing number of theories on the origin and evolution of religion have been put forward. Each one of these theories rests on a Darwinian framework but there is a lot of disagreement about which bits of the framework account best for the evolution of religion. Is religion primarily a by-product of some adaptation? Is it itself an adaptation, and if it is, does it benefi ciate individuals or groups? In this chapter, I review a number of theories that link religion to cooperation and show that these theories, contrary to what is often suggested in the literature, are not mutually exclusive. As I present each theory, I delineate an integrative framework that allows distinguishing the explanandum of each theory. Once this is done, it becomes clear that some theories provide good explanations for the origin of religion but not so good explanations for its maintenance and vice versa. Similarly some explanations are good explanations for the evolution of religious individual level traits but not so good explanations for traits hard to defi ne at the individual level. I suggest that to fully understand the religious phenomenon, integrating in a systematic way the different theories and the data is a more successful approach.
    Found 1 day, 2 hours ago on Pierrick Bourrat's site
  5. 97205.834806
    Reputation monitoring and the punishment of cheats are thought to be crucial to the viability and maintenance of human cooperation in large groups of non-kin. However, since the cost of policing moral norms must fall to those in the group, policing is itself a public good subject to exploitation by free riders. Recently, it has been suggested that belief in supernatural monitoring and punishment may discourage individuals from violating established moral norms and so facilitate human cooperation. Here we use cross-cultural survey data from a global sample of 87 countries to show that beliefs about two related sources of supernatural monitoring and punishment — God and the afterlife — independently predict respondents' assessment of the justifiability of a range of moral transgressions. This relationship holds even after controlling for frequency of religious participation, country of origin, religious denomination and level of education. As well as corroborating experimental work, our findings suggest that, across cultural and religious backgrounds, beliefs about the permissibility of moral transgressions are tied to beliefs about supernatural monitoring and punishment, supporting arguments that these beliefs may be important promoters of cooperation in human groups. © 2011 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
    Found 1 day, 3 hours ago on Pierrick Bourrat's site
  6. 100992.834822
    Hospital in Boston, Massachusetts. That report described the extraordinary surgery, immediately after birth, made possible by the use of computer—aided presurgical planning.1 The media picked up the story, and a first page arti— cle appeared in The New York Times on the same day.2 Two days earlier, on 8 August, conjoined twins were born in Malta in a case that stirred even more media attention. Eventually they underwent surgical separation in the Unit— ed Kingdom against the parents’ wishes.3
    Found 1 day, 4 hours ago on Peter Singer's site
  7. 101106.834837
    Reading Michael Fox’s "Animal Liberation: A Critique” in this issue was a chastening experience. In the past, when reading the complaints of authors that their critics have misunderstood them, I have tended to believe that some, at least, of the fault must lie with the author. If he has been misunderstood, he must have failed to make his views clear. Now that Fox’s article puts me in the position of complaining author, I wonder if my previous reactions were fair. I cannot find any obscurities in Animal Liberation which could have led Fox to his extraordinary presentation of "my" position.
    Found 1 day, 4 hours ago on Peter Singer's site
  8. 108118.834852
    In What a Plant Knows, Daniel Chamowitz reports what plant biologists apparently have known for a long time: although plants generally stay in one place (they’re sessile), they actively negotiate their environments. …
    Found 1 day, 6 hours ago on The Brains Blog
  9. 108621.834867
    Plato’s Sophist and Statesman use a notion of a model (paradeigma) quite different from the one with which we are familiar from dialogues like the Phaedo, Parmenides, and Timaeus. In those dialogues a paradeigma is a separate Form, an abstract perfect particular, whose nature is exhausted by its own character. Its participants are conceived as likenesses or images of it: they share with the Form the same character, but they also fall short of it because they exemplify not only that character but also its opposite. Mundane beautiful objects are plagued by various sorts of relativity—Helen is beautiful compared to other women, but not beautiful compared to a goddess; she is beautiful in her physical appearance, but not in her soul or her actions; she is beautiful in your eyes, but not in mine, and so on. The Form of the Beautiful, which is supposed to explain her beauty, is simply and unqualifiedly beautiful (Symp. 210e5-211d1).
    Found 1 day, 6 hours ago on Mary Louise Gill's site
  10. 213357.834886
    According to a number of theorists (Arpaly 2002, 2003; Arpaly and Schroeder 2014; Markovits 2010), a morally right action has moral worth if and only if it is performed for the right reasons, which are the reasons for which it is right, or the right-making features of the action. I have referred to morally worthy actions as “praiseworthy actions”, though, as we will see, perhaps “esteem-worthy actions” would be more precise, if one were to use Kantian terminology.
    Found 2 days, 11 hours ago on Nomy Arpaly's site
  11. 214434.834904
    We get angry for reasons—or, at any rate, for what we take to be reasons. If asked, why are you angry?” you will cite something (that you think) someone did, or failed to do. That action or omission—we can call it “bad behavior”—is what you are angry about. Getting angry is easy to understand: I behave badly towards you, that makes you angry, and now you are angry, at me, for my bad behavior. What is harder to understand is why you might cease to be angry.
    Found 2 days, 11 hours ago on Agnes Callard's site
  12. 280459.834922
    Some proponents of ‘experimental philosophy’ criticize philosophers’ use of thought experiments on the basis of evidence that the verdicts vary with truth-independent factors. However, their data concern the verdicts of philosophically untrained subjects. According to the expertise defence, what matters are the verdicts of trained philosophers, who are more likely to pay careful attention to the details of the scenario and track their relevance. In a recent paper, Jonathan Weinberg and others reply to the expertise defence that there is no evidence for such expertise. I reply to them in this paper, arguing that they have misconstrued the dialectical situation. Since they have produced no evidence that philosophical training is less efficacious for thought experimentation than for other cognitive tasks for which they acknowledge that it produces genuine expertise, such as informal argumentation, they have produced no evidence for treating the former more sceptically than the latter.
    Found 3 days, 5 hours ago on Tamler Sommers's site
  13. 284839.834938
    Scholars disagree about the nature of the doctrinal apparatus that supports Berkeley’s case for passive obedience to the sovereign. Is he a rule-utilitarian, or natural law theorist, or ethical egoist, or some combination of some or all these elements? Here I argue that Berkeley is an act-utilitarian who thinks that one is more likely to act rightly by following certain sorts of rules. I also argue that Berkeley mischaracterizes and misevaluates Locke’s version of the social contract theory. Finally, I consider the potentially practically self-defeating nature of Berkeley’s claim that there is no obligation to submit to the rule of “madmen” or “usurpers”.
    Found 3 days, 7 hours ago on Samuel Rickless's site
  14. 360709.834954
    This paper examines a constellation of ethical and editorial issues that have arisen since philosophers started to conduct, submit and publish empirical research. These issues encompass concerns over responsible authorship, fair treatment of human subjects, ethicality of experimental procedures, availability of data, unselective reporting and publishability of research findings. This study aims to assess whether the philosophical community has as yet successfully addressed such issues. To do so, the instructions for authors, submission process and published research papers of 29 main journals in philosophy have been considered and analyzed. In light of the evidence reported here, it is argued that the philosophical community has as yet failed to properly tackle such issues. The paper also delivers some recommendations for authors, reviewers and editors in the field.
    Found 4 days, 4 hours ago on PhilPapers
  15. 371429.834968
    One of the most remarkable features of moral properties is that they are, as W. D. Ross (1930, 28, 79, 88) used to put it, “resultant” or “consequential” attributes: they are properties that something can have only in virtue of having other properties. No action is brutely wrong: whenever I do something wrong, there are certain properties of that action (and, perhaps, of other features of the world as well) that make what I do wrong. Moreover, wrongness’s resultant or consequential nature has explanatory upshot: the features, whatever they are, that ground the wrongness of what I did also explain why it was wrong. We can view the familiar theoretical options in moral philosophy as offering competing accounts of what those features are: utilitarian versus Rossian versus Kantian versus . . . accounts of that in virtue of which right acts are right, blameworthy conduct is blameworthy, deplorable people are deplorable, etc. And usually the advocates of these accounts go about their theorizing by specifying moral principles that are taken to govern the moral properties being studied.
    Found 4 days, 7 hours ago on Selim Berker's site
  16. 374112.834984
    Behind the various Christian ideas about heaven and hell lies the more basic belief that our lives extend beyond the grave (see the entry on afterlife). For suppose that our lives do not extend beyond the grave. In addition to excluding a variety of ideas about reincarnation and karma, this would also preclude the very possibility of future compensation of any kind for those who experience horrendous evil during their earthly lives. Indeed, despite their profound differences, many Christians (though perhaps not all) and many atheists can presumably agree on one thing at least. If a young girl should be brutally raped and murdered and this should be the end of the story for the child, then a supremely powerful, benevolent, and just God would not exist.
    Found 4 days, 7 hours ago on Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  17. 385397.834998
    Image by Dick Thomas Johnson - flickr Let’s talk about Davecat. Davecat is the pseudonym of a Michigan-based man. He is married and has one mistress. Neither of them is human. They are both dolls — RealDolls to be precise. …
    Found 4 days, 11 hours ago on John Danaher's blog
  18. 448401.835015
    Welcome again to the Prosblogion Virtual Colloquium! This week’s paper is “Proportionality, Maximization, and the Highest Good” by Craig E. Bacon. Bacon is a PhD candidate at the University of South Carolina. …
    Found 5 days, 4 hours ago on The Prosblogion
  19. 506500.835035
    Philosophy of medicine is a field that seeks to explore fundamental issues in theory, research, and practice within the health sciences, particularly metaphysical and epistemological topics. Its historic roots arguably date back to ancient times, to the Hippocratic corpus among other sources, and there have been extended scholarly discussions on key concepts in the philosophy of medicine since at least the 1800s. Debates have occurred in the past over whether there is a distinct field rightly termed “philosophy of medicine” (e.g., Caplan 1992) but as there are now dedicated journals and professional organizations, a relatively well-established canon of scholarly literature, and distinctive questions and problems, it is defensible to claim that philosophy of medicine has now established itself.
    Found 5 days, 20 hours ago on Julian Reiss's site
  20. 512694.835049
    To have free will is to have what it takes to act freely. When an agent acts freely—when she exercises free will—it is up to her whether she does one thing or another on that occasion. A plurality of alternatives is open to her, and she determines which she pursues. When she does, she is an ultimate source or origin of her action. So runs a familiar conception of free will. Incompatibilists hold that we act freely in this sense only if determinism is false. Some say little more about what, besides indeterminism, free will requires. And, indeed, the task of providing an incompatibilist account is not an easy one.
    Found 5 days, 22 hours ago on Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  21. 512722.835064
    The ethical writings of the Oxford Idealists, T. H. Green and F. H. Bradley, reflect the influence of Kant and Hegel on English moral philosophy in the latter part of the Nineteenth Century. To the extent that either draws on other sources it is to Aristotle that they turn rather than to British moral philosophers such as Butler, Hume or Reid; a point which is evident both from the fact that Green and Bradley offer a type of perfectionist account of morality that is articulated in terms of the concept of self-realization and from the appearance of Aristotle's man of practical wisdom (the phronimos) in the fifth essay of Bradley's Ethical Studies.
    Found 5 days, 22 hours ago on Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  22. 521897.835079
    Alice has a paper due the day after Thanksgiving. She’s already gotten all the extensions she can, and she can’t get it done except by working through Thanksgiving. She is thinking of not going to the big Thanksgiving dinner that her grandfather organizes every year, even though it brings together relatives she hasn’t heard from for a long time, has much warm family fellowship, and great food. …
    Found 6 days ago on Alexander Pruss's Blog
  23. 605358.835094
    Torturing someone is gravely wrong because it causes grave harm to the victim, and the wickedness evinced in the act is typically proportional to the harm (as well as depending on many other factors). …
    Found 1 week ago on Alexander Pruss's Blog
  24. 605359.835109
    The ancient Chinese philosopher Mengzi and the early modern French philosopher Rousseau both argued that human nature is good. The ancient Chinese philosopher Xunzi and the early modern English philosopher Hobbes argued that human nature is not good. …
    Found 1 week ago on The Splintered Mind
  25. 733931.835126
    [Trigger Warning: This post is about trigger warnings] I have taught a number of controversial topics in my time. I have taught about the ethics of sex work, the criminalisation of incest, the problems of rape and sexual assault, the permissibility of torture, the effectiveness of the death penalty, the problems of racial profiling and bias in the criminal justice system, and the natural law argument against homosexuality (to name but a few). …
    Found 1 week, 1 day ago on John Danaher's blog
  26. 735318.835143
    The petition against Donald Trump’s ‘state visit’ to the United Kingdom has gathered over 1.8 million signatories. (I am one of them). Of particular concern to many of these signatories has been Trump’s ‘Muslim ban’, and its perceived infringement of international human rights law. …
    Found 1 week, 1 day ago on Justice Everywhere
  27. 735321.835161
    Reliabilism about justified belief comes in two varieties: process reliabilism and indicator reliabilism. According to process reliabilism, a belief is justified if it is formed by a process that is likely to produce truths; according to indicator reliabilism, a belief is justified if it likely to be true given the ground on which the belief is based. …
    Found 1 week, 1 day ago on M-Phi
  28. 1170748.835177
    Pornography is now ubiquitous. If you have an internet connection, you have access to a virtually inexhaustible supply of the stuff. Debates rage over whether this is a good or bad thing. There are long-standing research programmes in psychology and philosophy that focus on the ethical and social consequences of exposure to pornography. …
    Found 1 week, 6 days ago on John Danaher's blog
  29. 1287602.835193
    Impartiality is sometimes treated by philosophers as if it were equivalent to moral impartiality. Or, at the very least, the former word is often used, without the qualifying adjective ‘moral’, even when it is the particularly moral concept that is intended. This is misleading, since impartiality in its broadest sense is best understood as a formal notion, while moral impartiality in particular is a substantive concept – and one concerning which there is considerable dispute. This entry will be predominantly concerned with moral impartiality – the sort of impartiality, that is, that commonly features in normative moral and political theories.
    Found 2 weeks ago on Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  30. 1379119.835208
    I've been waffling about this for years (e.g., here and here). Today, I'll try out a multi-dimensional answer. 1. My first thought is that it would be unfair for us to hold ethics professors to higher standards of personal behavior because of their career choice. …
    Found 2 weeks, 1 day ago on The Splintered Mind