1. 16381.103465
    In this paper, we present an agent-based model for studying the impact of ‘myside bias’ on the argumentative dynamics in scientific communities. Recent insights in cognitive science suggest that scientific reasoning is influenced by ‘myside bias’. This bias manifests as a tendency to prioritize the search and generation of arguments that support one’s views rather than arguments that undermine them. Additionally, individuals tend to apply more critical scrutiny to opposing stances than to their own. Although myside bias may pull individual scientists away from the truth, its effects on communities of reasoners remain unclear. The aim of our model is two-fold: first, to study the argumentative dynamics generated by myside bias, and second, to explore which mechanisms may act as a mitigating factor against its pernicious effects. Our results indicate that biased communities are epistemically less successful than non-biased ones, and that they also tend to be less polarized than non-biased ones. Moreover, we find that two socio-epistemic mechanisms help communities to mitigate the effect of the bias: the presence of a common filter on weak arguments, which can be interpreted as shared beliefs, and an equal distribution of agents for each alternative at the start of the scientific debate.
    Found 4 hours, 33 minutes ago on PhilSci Archive
  2. 16403.103547
    Apologies serve important moral and social functions such as expressing remorse, taking responsibility, and repairing trusting relationships. LLM-based chatbots routinely produce output which has the linguistic form of an apology. However, chatbots are not the kind of linguistic or moral agents that could perform any of the functions listed above. KEYWORDS: chatbots, apologies, large language models, bullshit Especially since the release of ChatGPT in late 2022, there has been a furor about chatbots powered by Large Language Models (LLMs). Much of the concern has been directed at the problem of hallucination or confabulation, the tendency of chatbots to produce outputs which look like assertions but which have no connection to the truth. It is common to suggest that the output of chatbots is bullshit in the somewhat technical sense defined by Harry Frankfurt. Chatbot outputs which are not declarative sentences have received less attention. Our focus here is on apologies.
    Found 4 hours, 33 minutes ago on PhilSci Archive
  3. 16433.103563
    Wilfrid Sellars’ distinctive mid-20th century version of scientific realism has lately been gaining ground. There has been growing appreciation of how, by means of his critique of the Myth of the Given, Sellars highlights profound problems in the representationalism (or descriptivism – we treat these terms as equivalent) that mainstream realisms have taken for granted. Representationalism may be broadly understood as the idea that statements count as true exactly insofar as corresponding discrete portions of reality (‘truth-makers’) exist. The problem Sellars saw with representationalist realisms is that although they posit the existence of many entities, they leave unexplained: i) how our language manages to ‘denote’ these entities, when it would appear that linguistic and worldly items are quite unlike one another, ii) how the worldly items (both particulars and general properties) are individuated. With synoptic ambition rare in his era, Sellars set out to extract the tangled hedge of representationalism by its root, and develop a new, properly naturalistic, account of concept-formation in its place.
    Found 4 hours, 33 minutes ago on PhilSci Archive
  4. 30780.103576
    Fabian Hundertmark, Bielefeld University Jakob Roloff, Justus-Liebig-University Gießen Francesca Bellazzi, University of Oslo, ERC Project Assembling Life (no.101089326) 1. Introduction In the target post, Dong and Piccinini criticize SE and propose a new goal-contribution account of functions (GCA) (also in Maley, Piccinini 2017; Piccinini, 2020). …
    Found 8 hours, 33 minutes ago on The Brains Blog
  5. 30780.103594
    Preliminary Note: As usual, the end of the year is hectic, and I’m spending quite some time preparing special content for this newsletter that should be ready for Christmas Eve. Posting should be light until then, and today’s post is more a digression from my usual topics than anything else. …
    Found 8 hours, 33 minutes ago on The Archimedean Point
  6. 88748.103644
    Andrew Bailey formulated and defended the Priority Principle (PP), that we think our thoughts in a primary rather than inherited way. His main argument for PP is a two-thinkers argument: if I think my thoughts in an inherited way, then something else—the thing I inherit the thoughts from—thinks them as well, but there aren’t two thinkers of my thoughts. …
    Found 1 day ago on Alexander Pruss's Blog
  7. 111200.103656
    In an old post, I said that Goodman and Quine can’t define the concept of an infinite number of objects using their logical resources. Allen Hazen corrected me in a comment in the specific context of defining infinite sentences. …
    Found 1 day, 6 hours ago on Alexander Pruss's Blog
  8. 124871.103668
    The commentators in this Special Issue on ‘Epistemology, ontology, and scientific realism’ raise substantial questions about, and objections to, central aspects of my own thinking about semirealism (a proposal for how best to formulate scientific realism), as well as the larger philosophical context in which debates about scientific realism unfold. This larger context concerns the nature of realism more generally and the epistemic stances that underlie our considered opinions of what the sciences are telling us about the ontology of the world. In this paper, I consider my critics’ remarks, and endeavor to lay their criticisms to rest.
    Found 1 day, 10 hours ago on Anjan Chakravartty's site
  9. 168279.103678
    Comonotonicity (“same variation”) of random variables minimizes hedging possibilities and has been widely used, e.g., in Gilboa and Schmeidler’s ambiguity models. This paper investigates anticomonotonicity (“opposite variation”; abbreviated “AC”), the natural counterpart to comonotonicity. It minimizes leveraging rather than hedging possibilities. Surprisingly, AC restrictions of several traditional axioms do not give new models. Instead, they strengthen the foundations of existing classical models: (a) linear functionals through Cauchy’s equation; (b) Anscombe-Aumann expected utility; (c) as-if-risk-neutral pricing through no-arbitrage; (d) de Finetti’s bookmaking foundation of Bayesianism using subjective probabilities; (e) risk aversion in Savage’s subjective expected utility. In each case, our generalizations show where the critical tests of classical axioms lie: in the AC cases (maximal hedges). We next present examples where AC restrictions do essentially weaken existing axioms, and do provide new properties and new models.
    Found 1 day, 22 hours ago on Peter P. Wakker's site
  10. 180057.103688
    In the semantic debate about perspectival expressions—predicates of taste, aesthetic and moral terms, epistemic modals, etc.—intuitions about armchair scenarios (e.g., disagreement, retraction) have played a crucial role. More recently, various experimental studies have been conducted, both in relation to disagreement (e.g., Cova, 2012; Foushee and Srinivasan, 2017; Solt, 2018) and retraction (e.g., Knobe and Yalcin, 2014; Khoo, 2018; Beddor and Egan, 2018; Dinges and Zakkou, 2020; Kneer 2021; 2022; Almagro, Bordonaba Plou, and Villanueva, 2023; Marques, 2024), with the aim of establishing a more solid foundation for semantic theorizing. Both these types of data have been used to argue for or against certain views (e.g., contextualism, relativism). In this talk, I discern a common thread in the use of these data and argue for two claims: (i) which perspective is adopted by those judging the armchair scenarios put forward and by the participants in experimental studies crucially matters for the viability of the intended results; (ii) failure to properly attend to this puts recent experimental work at risk. Finally, I consider the case of cross-linguistic disagreement and retraction and assess their importance for the semantic debate about perspectival expressions, as well as for the claim that perspective matters in putting forward the data on which decisions about the right semantic view are made.
    Found 2 days, 2 hours ago on Dan Zeman's site
  11. 183912.103699
    The earliest works of political theory precede Athenian democracy—the traditional starting point of Anglophone histories of political thought—by over two millennia. More time passed between the first written accounts of government in Mesopotamia and the birth of Plato than has passed between Plato ’s life and ours. And yet this “other half” of the history of political thought has barely registered in the academic field of political theory. This article seeks to “reset” the starting point of the field back to its earliest origins in ancient Sumer. Beginning then and there opens a new vista on the history of political thought by restoring questions of public administration to the foreground of the field. For while the ancient Athenians enslaved their bureaucrats and wrote almost nothing about them, the analogous actors were free and highly valued in ancient Mesopotamian political culture. It was these scribal administrators who invented the world ’s first literature and written political thought. In their writings, they valorized their own administrative labor and the public goods that it alone could produce as objects of wonder and enchantment. From this vantage point, the article calls for a new research agenda that will expand political theory’s recent “rediscovery” of bureaucracy by recovering public administration as a major thematic throughline in the five-thousand-year global history of human political ideas. Understanding public administration as an integral part of large-scale human societies from the very beginning may help to counter oligarchic claims in contemporary democracies that bureaucracy is a recent alien imposition.
    Found 2 days, 3 hours ago on Henry Farrell's site
  12. 185811.103716
    A sentential connective is said to be univocal, relative to a formal system F for a sentential logic containing iff any two connectives 1 and 2 which satisfy the same F rules (and axioms) as are such that similar formulas involving ⋆ and ⋆2 are inter-derivable in F . To be more precise, suppose is a unary connective. Then is univocal relative to F iff for any 1 and 2 satisfying the same principles as in F, we have 1α ⊢F 2 . And, if is binary, then is univocal relative to F iff for any 1 and 2 satisfying the same principles as in F , we have α ⋆1 ⊢F α ⋆2 . In order to illustrate this definition of univocity, it is helpful to begin with a simple historical example.
    Found 2 days, 3 hours ago on Branden Fitelson's site
  13. 185850.103726
    There seems to be such a thing as property inheritance, where x inherits a property F from y which has F in a non-derivative way. Here are some examples of this phenomenon on various theories: I inherit mass from my molecules. …
    Found 2 days, 3 hours ago on Alexander Pruss's Blog
  14. 189340.103736
    This paper interrogates the concept of luck in cancer diagnosis. I argue that while it might have some utility for individuals, at the clinical and research level, the concept impedes important prevention efforts and misdirects sources of blame in a cancer diagnosis. Such use, in fact, has the possibility of harming already vulnerable efforts at ameliorating social determinants of health and should therefore be eliminated from research and clinical contexts.
    Found 2 days, 4 hours ago on PhilSci Archive
  15. 198355.103746
    Yesterday I arrived in Santa Clara for the Q2B (Quantum 2 Business) conference, which starts this morning, and where I’ll be speaking Thursday on “Quantum Algorithms in 2024: How Should We Feel?” and also closing the conference via an Ask-Us-Anything session with John Preskill. …
    Found 2 days, 7 hours ago on Scott Aaronson's blog
  16. 245562.103756
    We set up a general framework for higher order probabilities. A simple HOP (Higher Order Probability space) consists of a probability space and an operation PR, such that, for every event A and every real closed interval A, PR(A ,A) is the event that A’s "true" probability lies in A. (The "true" probability can be construed here either as the objective probability, or the probability assigned by an expert, or the one assigned eventually in a fuller state of knowledge.) In a general HOP the operation PR has also an additional argument ranging over an ordered set of time-points, or, more generally, over a partially ordered set of stages; PR({A,t,A) is the event that A's probability at stage ¢ lies in 4. First we investigate simple HOPs and then the general ones. Assuming some intuitively justified axioms, we derive the most general structure of such a space. We also indicate various connections with modal logic.
    Found 2 days, 20 hours ago on Haim Gaifman's site
  17. 287171.103766
    The debate over God’s existence starts to look very different once you take on board the following insight: We should not expect a perfect being to create the best possible world (or universe), but rather the best possible multiverse. …
    Found 3 days, 7 hours ago on Good Thoughts
  18. 395281.103777
    Welcome to the December leisurely cruise: Wherever we are sailing, assume that it’s warm. This is an overview of our first set of readings for December from my Statistical Inference as Severe Testing: How to get beyond the statistics wars (CUP 2018): [SIST]–Excursion 3 Tour II–(although I already snuck in one of the examples from 3.4, Cox’s weighing machine). …
    Found 4 days, 13 hours ago on D. G. Mayo's blog
  19. 420066.103789
    Theories of ‘actual causation’ aim to provide an informative guide for assessing which events cause which others in circumstances where almost everything else is known: which other events occurred or did not occur, and how (if at all) the occurrence or non-occurrence of a particular event (regarded as values of a variable) can depend on speci c other events (or their absence), also regarded as values of variables. The ultimate aim is a theory that can agreeably be applied in causally fraught circumstances of technology, the law, and everyday life, where the identi cation of relevant features is not immediate and judgements of causation are entwined with judgements of moral or legal responsibility. Joseph Halpern’s Actual Causality is the latest and most extensive addition to this e ort, carried out in a tradition that holds causation to be di erence making.
    Found 4 days, 20 hours ago on PhilSci Archive
  20. 420094.103802
    Should metaphysics be informed by the results of contemporary science? Should it be naturalized? The debate surrounding these and similar questions is one of the most vigorous in contemporary theoretical philosophy. However, until now many positions have only been roughly sketched out, and there has been very limited dialogue between the proponents of naturalization and the defenders of traditional metaphysics. This is unfortunate, considering the fact that the status and legitimacy of an entire philosophical sub-discipline is at stake.
    Found 4 days, 20 hours ago on PhilSci Archive
  21. 420121.103816
    Ryckman’s work derives its generic title from its being part of the series Routledge Philosophers, which features monographs on philosophers from Plato to Heidegger. His opening statement that ‘Einstein was a theoretical physicist, not a philosopher in any customary sense’ (p. 1) seems an unnecessarily apologetic start since, among the Routledge philosophers, we also nd Sigmund Freud and Charles Darwin, neither of whom would count as ‘philosophers in any customary sense’. But their work, like Einstein’s, has profoundly transformed our understanding of the world and, like Einstein, they have articulated explicit re ections that might well be classi ed as philosophical.
    Found 4 days, 20 hours ago on PhilSci Archive
  22. 420148.103828
    Debates on the ontology of space used to gesture at some root in history—of philosophical groundings of dynamics and gravitation theory—a history as old as the physics it engaged with. In our century, however, this tribute to the philosophical past has become an absent-minded nod, a ritual invocation of credos whose real origins are now occulted by mythopoiesis. A regrettable outcome, in many ways, but not entirely unexpected. History of philosophy of science has matured greatly, and the threshold of admission to its peerage has gone up dramatically—it is now too high for most full-time workers in ‘general’ philosophy of science to pass. Conversely, the latter eld has taken a broadly naturalistic bent, and turned away from (philosophical) history as a source of insight. Instead, it often nds analytic metaphysics a more congenial interlocutor. Hard-headed spectators might nd it a bit self-serving; historians are a demanding bunch, whereas latter-day metaphysicians are kind to anyone who does not mind relying on personal intuitions.
    Found 4 days, 20 hours ago on PhilSci Archive
  23. 420175.10384
    This collection of nine free-standing essays o ers a fresh perspective on science and language and a fascinating critique of much of contemporary philosophy. The essays can be grouped as follows: Chapter 1 serves as an introduction and a brief for pragmatism; Chapters 2 and 5 concern science; Chapters 3 and 4 deal with historical gures (Leibniz and Duhem); Chapters 6 and 7 critique contemporary analytic metaphysics; and Chapters 8 and 9 discuss language and mathematics. The style is opinionated, contrarian, humorous, and expansive. The essays focus on case studies that develop in detail some of the themes of Wilson’s earlier Wandering Signi cance ([2006]). Though they avoid general dogma, they re ect a uni ed critical perspective organized around puzzles that emerge when one considers the ‘how’ and ‘why’ of the practical successes that attend conceptual development in applied mathematics. Those already familiar with Wilson’s work will appreciate the novel developments in this long-awaited publication; those new to his work, despite its sometimes technical challenges and hard-to-tame aspects, will nd ample reward in the surprising new light it sheds on contemporary philosophical issues in language and science.
    Found 4 days, 20 hours ago on PhilSci Archive
  24. 420230.103853
    For a few years now there have been strange rumblings emanating from Exeter. Many of them have been coming from the Centre for the Study of Life Sciences, Egenis, and the process philosophy research-group set up by John Dupré and Daniel J. Nicholson, with Stephan Guttinger and Anne Sophie Meincke. Nicholson and Dupré are the editors of this collection, and its publication marks the conclusion of their ve-year ‘PROBIO’ project, collecting together the contributions from their rst major workshop, ‘Process Philosophy of Biology’, alongside others. And while they may object to the suggested metaphysical implication, I’m happy to say this is a substantial contribution to discussions of process in analytic philosophy of biology.
    Found 4 days, 20 hours ago on PhilSci Archive
  25. 420259.103865
    The publication of Saunders Mac Lane’s ([1971]) Categories for the Working Mathematician (CWM) was a signal event in the history of category theory. This in uential textbook grew out of the recognition that there had emerged a well-established body of material that one might consider ‘basic’ category theory, and that it provided an architecture of concepts (such as categories, functors, limits, and adjoints) that uni ed many areas of mathematics. One of the explicit aims of CWM was thus to transmit this meta-mathematical lingua franca to mathematicians in other sub elds.
    Found 4 days, 20 hours ago on PhilSci Archive
  26. 420288.103879
    Is philosophy of science best carried out at a ne-grained level, focusing on the theories and methods of individual sciences? Or is there still room for a general philosophy of science, for the study of philosophical questions about science as such? For Samuel Schindler, the answer to the last question is a resounding ‘yes!’, and his book Theoretical Virtues in Science is an unapologetic attempt to grapple with what he regards as three key questions for philosophy of science-in-general: What are the features—the virtues—that characterize good scienti c theories? What role do these virtues play in scienti c inquiry? And what do they allow us, as philosophers, to conclude about reality?
    Found 4 days, 20 hours ago on PhilSci Archive
  27. 420316.1039
    The historical sciences appear to present a challenge for mainstream views about the epistemology of science, which have largely been developed with the physical sciences in mind. While debates over realism about microphysical entities still continue, what are we to make of the epistemic situation of historical scientists? The objects of their investigation, namely, historical entities and processes, are, like microphysical entities, not directly observable, but unlike microphysical entities, they are unmanipulable. As Derek Turner ([2007]) has argued, this appears to put historical scientists in a worse situation, epistemically, than microphysicists. But most philosophers (I presume) would not want to be anti-realists about the entities and processes of the past. What, then, is the proper attitude we should have towards the historical sciences? And might thinking about this question provide us with insights that we could direct back towards more traditional debates about the epistemology of science?
    Found 4 days, 20 hours ago on PhilSci Archive
  28. 447962.103913
    In 1979 Bob Dylan became a born again Christian, and worse, released three albums of songs about God. About this perceived betrayal, I was too young to have an opinion; it was part of a lore I learned much later. …
    Found 5 days, 4 hours ago on Mostly Aesthetics
  29. 471174.103929
    Expected value maximization gives plausible guidance for moral decision-making under uncertainty in many situations. But it has extremely unappetizing implications in ‘Pascalian’ situations involving tiny probabilities of extreme outcomes. This paper shows, first, that under realistic levels of ‘background uncertainty’ about sources of value independent of one’s present choice, a widely accepted and apparently innocuous principle—stochastic dominance—requires that prospects be ranked by the expected value of their consequences in most ordinary choice situations. But second, this implication does not hold when differences in expected value are driven by tiny probabilities of extreme outcomes. Stochastic dominance therefore lets us draw a surprisingly principled line between ‘ordinary’ and ‘Pascalian’ situations, providing a powerful justification for de facto expected value maximization in the former context while permitting deviations in the latter. Drawing this distinction is incompatible with an in-principle commitment to maximizing expected value, but does not require too much departure from decision-theoretic orthodoxy: it is compatible, for instance, with the view that moral agents must maximize the expectation of a utility function that is an increasing function of moral value.
    Found 5 days, 10 hours ago on Christian Tarsney's site
  30. 478160.103945
    Is stand-up comedy akin to psychotherapy? Yes, argues psychoanalyst Nuar Alsadir in Animal Joy: As part of my research … I had frequented comedy clubs and noticed how each performance, had it been delivered in a different tone of voice and context, could have been the text of a therapy session. …
    Found 5 days, 12 hours ago on Under the Net