1. 7765.385795
    I debate immigration habitually. Whenever there’s before-and-after voting, I always lose. No matter how leftist the audience is, the anti-immigration side need only warn “Immigration could hurt some Americans” to flip the vote. …
    Found 2 hours, 9 minutes ago on Bet On It
  2. 19906.385851
    Polysemy is a phenomenon involving single lexical items with multiple related senses. Much theorizing about it has focused on developing linguistic accounts that are responsive to various compositional and representational challenges in semantics and psychology. We focus on an underexplored question: Why does systematic polysemy cluster in the ways it does? That is, why do we see certain regular patterns of sense multiplicity, but not others? Drawing on an independently motivated view of kind cognition—i.e., the formal structures for different classes of kind representations—we argue for an answer centered on conceptual individuation. Specifically, we argue that classes of kind concepts vary in what they individuate (i.e., counting as one and specifying what makes it the same or different from others). By elucidating these differences, we can explain why a range of patterns of systematic polysemy are found cross-linguistically and why other patterns are not attested. Overall, our account provides an explanatory framework addressing an important question at the interface between language and mind and opens new avenues for future theoretical and empirical research.
    Found 5 hours, 31 minutes ago on Katherine Ritchie's site
  3. 19935.385863
    We start with an observation about implicit quantifier domain restriction: certain implicit restrictions (e.g., restricting objects by location and time) appear to be more natural and widely available than others (e.g., restricting objects by color, aesthetic, or historical properties). Our aim is to explain why this is. That is, we aim to explain why some implicit domain restriction possibilities are available by default. We argue that, regardless of their other explanatory virtues, extant pragmatic and metasemantic frameworks leave this question unanswered. We then motivate a partially nativist account of domain restriction that involves a minimal view of joint planning around broad shared goals about navigating and influencing our environments augmented with cognitive heuristics that facilitate these. Finally, we sketch how the view can be extended to account for the ways non-default restriction possibilities become available when conversationalists have shared idiosyncratic goals.
    Found 5 hours, 32 minutes ago on Katherine Ritchie's site
  4. 58679.385871
    Assume actual result utilitarianism on which there are facts of the matter about what would transpire given any possible action of mine, and an action is right just in case it has the best consequences. …
    Found 16 hours, 17 minutes ago on Alexander Pruss's Blog
  5. 88490.385878
    Having previously lamented the (unnecessary) conceptual limitations of the utilitarian tradition, it’s time to turn to the rival deontological tradition. Whereas many utilitarians focus on value to the point of neglecting other significant normative concepts, my sense is that deontologists’ hyper-focus on permissibility can lead to similar problems. …
    Found 1 day ago on Good Thoughts
  6. 92291.385884
    I discuss reproducibility issues in animal-based research in biomedicine and scrutinize the notion that the causes of non-reproducible results are the same as in other disciplines. I argue that there are aspects characteristic of animal experimentation that are important for analysing reproducibility problems but have not yet been discussed in this context. Using an approach that integrates epistemological and ethical questions, I explore these aspects and show that the prevalent focus on questionable research practices and methodological reforms falls short in understanding and managing key challenges to reproducibility in animal-based biomedicine.
    Found 1 day, 1 hour ago on PhilSci Archive
  7. 92319.385891
    Canonically, ‘classic’ tests of general relativity (GR) include perihelion pre-cession, the bending of light around stars, and gravitational redshift; ‘modern’ tests have to do with, inter alia, relativistic time delay, equivalence principle tests, gravitational lensing, strong field gravity, and gravitational waves. The orthodoxy is that both classic and modern tests of GR afford experimental confirmation of that theory in particular. In this article, we question this orthodoxy, by showing there are classes of both relativistic theories (with spatiotemporal geometrical properties different from those of GR) and non-relativistic theories (in which the lightcones of a relativistic spacetime are ‘widened’) which would also pass such tests. Thus, (a) issues of underdetermination in the context of GR loom much larger than one might have thought, and (b) given this, one has to think more carefully about what exactly such tests in fact are testing.
    Found 1 day, 1 hour ago on PhilSci Archive
  8. 149043.385897
    The Octoberfest is a noble tradition in category theory: a low-key, friendly conference for researchers to share their work and thoughts. This year it’s on Saturday October 26th and Sunday October 27th. …
    Found 1 day, 17 hours ago on Azimuth
  9. 172285.385903
    The passage of time undoubtedly complicates questions of the rights and duties that are owed as a result of past wrongdoing. Writing in 2001, Janna Thompson outlines what she called the “Exclusion Principle,” claiming, “It is a principle basic to reparative justice . . . that individuals or collectives are entitled to reparation only if they were the ones to whom the injustice was done.” She continues, “It is also part of the Exclusion Principle that only perpetrators, whether these are groups or individuals, should be punished for injustice or required to make recompense.” This is the central challenge faced by accounts of reparative justice relating to historic injustice: What, if anything, can be owed today if some or all of the original perpetrators and victims are dead? I here assess Andrew I. Cohen’s recent work on apologies for historic injustice. His account, I will argue, is both persuasive and far-reaching—indeed, more far-reaching than Cohen suggests. Some might think that this renders the theory implausible; to the contrary, I argue that this is the right way to confront the vast scale of historic wrongdoing.
    Found 1 day, 23 hours ago on Reason Papers
  10. 172311.385909
    In his Apologies and Moral Repair, Andrew I. Cohen has given us a wonderful piece of moral philosophizing. It is in my view the best sort of contribution moral philosophy can make. He examines closely an important (even though mundane) moral practice: the practice of apologizing. He attempts to understand what apologies are, what makes them appropriate, what makes them successful (when they are), and other aspects of this practice. Since human beings treat one another badly so very often (sometimes inadvertently, sometimes not), apologies are an important lubricant for decent and peaceful social life. What is more, as I shall argue, we can learn something important about ourselves from considering them.
    Found 1 day, 23 hours ago on Reason Papers
  11. 172438.385915
    David Schmidtz has long been one of the best writers in political philosophy, remarkably managing to defend his ideas with analytic precision without sacrificing readability. In Living Together, he continues that while providing us with a masterful work that harks back to classical liberals such as John Locke, David Hume, Adam Smith, and John Stuart Mill. In doing so, he offers a model of what scholars of PPE (Philosophy, Politics, and Economics) should strive for: clarity of writing and philosophical acuity matched with clear appreciation of the best social science available to describe and analyze what we want from a social, political, and economic order (hereafter “the social order”).
    Found 1 day, 23 hours ago on Reason Papers
  12. 172465.385921
    Rawls’s claim that “justice is the first virtue of social institutions” (p. 24). To the contrary, Schmidtz writes: “The first thing we need from institutions is a settled framework of mutual expectation that keeps the peace well enough to foster conditions that enable society to be a cooperative venture for mutual benefit” (p. 24). Several pages earlier, though, he says that “[j]ustice enables people to navigate the social world” (p. 19), which sounds a lot like “the first thing we need from institutions” (p. 24), and four pages earlier he tells us that “Humean justice is not everything—not even close—but almost everything depends on it” (p. 20). If “almost everything depends on” justice, why isn’t it “the first virtue of social institutions”?
    Found 1 day, 23 hours ago on Reason Papers
  13. 172565.385928
    David Schmidtz’s book Living Together contains rich discussions of several important topics in political philosophy, political economy, legal philosophy, and moral philosophy. The overall theme tying these topics together is that our theories must be realistic, based on empirical evidence. Ideal theories ignore this. A famous example of such a theory is John Rawls’s second principle of justice—the difference principle—in his A Theory of Justice. In spite of its counterintuitive nature, Rawls assumes that everyone will comply with it.
    Found 1 day, 23 hours ago on Reason Papers
  14. 261544.385934
    I claim that there is no general, straightforward and satisfactory way to define a total comparative probability with the standard axioms using full conditional probabilities. By a “straightforward” way, I mean something like: - A ≲ B iff P(A−B|AΔB) ≤ P(B−A|AΔB) (De Finetti) or: - A ≲ B iff P(A|A∪B) ≤ P(A|A∪B) (Pruss). …
    Found 3 days ago on Alexander Pruss's Blog
  15. 265247.385941
    The question of whether chemical structure is reducible to Everettian Quantum Mechanics (EQM) should be of interest to philosophers of chemistry and philosophers of physics alike. Among the three realist interpretations of quantum mechanics, EQM resolves the measurement problem by claiming that measurements (now interpreted as instances of decoherence) have indeterminate outcomes absolutely speaking, but determinate outcomes relative to emergent worlds (Maudlin, 1995). Philosophers who wish to be sensitive to the practice of quantum chemistry (e.g. Scerri, 2016) should be interested in EQM because Franklin and Seifert (2020) claim that resolving the measurement problem also resolves the reducibility of chemical structure, and EQM is the interpretation which involves no mathematical structure beyond that used by practicing scientists. Philosophers interested in the quantum interpretation debate should be interested in the reducibility of chemistry because chemical structure is precisely the kind of determinate three-dimensional fact which EQM should be able to ground if it is to be empirically coherent (see Allori, 2023). The prospects for reduction of chemical structure are poor if it cannot succeed in EQM; the prospects for EQM as a guide to ontology are poor if it cannot reduce chemical structure.
    Found 3 days, 1 hour ago on PhilSci Archive
  16. 265274.385946
    Levels-of-reality talk is common among practicing scientists and philosophers of science, yet such talk of levels has been criticized by Jaegwon Kim, Amie Thomasson, and Angela Potochnik, which I analyze into three objections of increasing strength. The first requires abandoning only some of the wilder claims about levels, while the second prunes off many biological uses, and the third poses serious challenges even for metaphysicians. Metaphysicians who wish to save realism about levels must be prepared to make serious revisions. I argue for a novel approach which carves up levels using a neo-Aristotelian answer to the question of fundamental mereology which takes substances as the tiles of the world and uses metaphysical priority aconformities these generate in the mereological graph to identify levels. This emergentist account of levels is more coherent than varieties less connected to mereological structure, and places fewer constraints on that mereological structure than views like van Inwagen’s. While starkly revisionist, it fares better in recovering historical levels discourse than competitors like material atomism and priority monism. Further, the most painful revision is treating much of the biological levels discourse as representation and metaphor, but Potochnik argues that such talk was never a good candidate for metaphysics.
    Found 3 days, 1 hour ago on PhilSci Archive
  17. 265308.385952
    The mechanistic approach in the cognitive and biological sciences emphasizes that scientific explanations succeed by analyzing the mechanisms underlying phenomena across multiple levels. In this paper, we propose a formal strategy to establish such multi-level mechanistic models, which are foundational to mechanistic explanations. Our objectives are twofold: First, we introduce the novel "mLCA" (multi-Level Coincidence Analysis) script, which transforms binary data tables from tests on mechanistic systems into mechanistic models consistent with those tables. Second, we provide several philosophical insights derived from the outcomes generated by this script and its underlying algorithm. Using illustrative examples, we defend the following claims: 1. Inference methods for generating mechanistic models generally require information on how causal factors are assigned to different levels within data tables generated by multi-level structures. 2. The mLCA script successfully produces appropriate mechanistic models from binary data tables, demonstrating the practical application of the philosophical mechanistic approach in the sciences. 3. The number of solutions generated by mLCA increases significantly as the number of relevant factors grows, reflecting adaptations in causal inference methods to meet the demands of multi-level mechanistic modeling. 4. Any further reduction of solutions, if possible, involves pragmatic considerations, a point that carries profound implications for the broader ambitions of the mechanistic approach. By addressing these points, our paper contributes both to the development of practical algorithmic tools and to a deeper philosophical understanding of multi-level mechanistic modeling.
    Found 3 days, 1 hour ago on PhilSci Archive
  18. 265337.385959
    This paper investigates whether the philosophical supervenience problem has any bearing on the economic sciences. It first reconstructs some examples of economics normal science that aim at a correct description and explanation of causes of observable phenomena in an economic reference system. Subsequently, the supervenience problem is presented as it is known from the philosophy of biology and the philosophy of mind. A formulation of the problem for economic causes is then developed in an analogous way, even though the ontological commitments of economics are less obvious. The main hypotheses defended in this paper are the following ones: (i) Economic models are amenable to causal interpretations and (ii) the efficacy of economic causes characterized by such models is fundamentally problematic from a metaphysical point of view, analogously to that of biological and mental causes. Moreover, it is shown that (iii) the problem of causal exclusion is even more drastic for economic causes than for biological or mental causes due to a non-localizability and an overlap of economic events.
    Found 3 days, 1 hour ago on PhilSci Archive
  19. 265365.385966
    This paper focuses on two arguments recently developed in the literature against the interpretation of rational choice theory as an empirical theory. It starts with a reconstruction of a historical analysis, according to which rational choice theory has mostly been used in the past as a methodological principle and rarely as a deep empirical theory. In a next step, it challenges an argument found in the literature that social and economic phenomena are ontically emergent and that they by themselves can enter genuine explanations. Subsequently, it criticizes the methodological assumption about the irrelevance of psychological mechanisms of the individual for economic models. The main reason offered is the observation that such models, even if predictively adequate, will be very limited in their explanatory power. The overall conclusion of the paper is that rational choice theory ought to be treated as a theory after all − and potentially extended by future empirical research.
    Found 3 days, 1 hour ago on PhilSci Archive
  20. 279466.385972
    1: Caravaggio, in his religious art, reminded people that these miracles had transpired neither in primary colors, nor in brilliantly hued paintings of sanitized saints and celestial fireworks, but in dusty streets and dark rooms much like the streets and rooms in which they lived. …
    Found 3 days, 5 hours ago on Mostly Aesthetics
  21. 295561.385978
    It’s been a while since I wrote about my online reading. In part, that’s because I’ve had less time to keep up with the magazines I like, in part because I’ve been unusually hard to entertain— in a dull state of nerves, such as everybody is occasionally liable to; unsusceptible to enjoyment or pleasurable excitement; one of those moods when what is pleasure at other times, becomes insipid or indifferent. …
    Found 3 days, 10 hours ago on Under the Net
  22. 318105.385984
    According to most writers on lying, to lie is to assert something one believes to be false, as captured by what is sometimes called “The Assertion-Based Definition of Lying:” The Assertion-Based Definition of Lying (AL) A lies to B if and only if there is a proposition p such that (AL1) A asserts that p, and (AL2) A believes that p is false.
    Found 3 days, 16 hours ago on Andreas Stokke's site
  23. 318130.38599
    This paper examines a form of talking about speech acts, mental states, and other features so far unexplored in philosophy: quotative be like. Quotative be like is the use of like and to be that occurs in constructions such as "Ellen was like "I'm leaving!"" We argue that neglect of quotative be like represents a gap in our understanding of our ways of characterizing the minds and speech of ourselves and others. Further, we show that quotative be like is not reducible to more familiar forms of direct discourse or indirect discourse. Mapping out a number of different options for theorizing about quotative be like, we argue for an account on which the quoted material in quotative be like picks out properties.
    Found 3 days, 16 hours ago on Andreas Stokke's site
  24. 353567.385995
    [#4 in my series of excerpts from Questioning Beneficence: Four Philosophers on Effective Altruism and Doing Good. ]1 How much should we care about future people? Total utilitarians answer, “Equally to our concern for presently-existing people.” Narrow person-affecting theorists answer, “Not at all”—at least in a disturbingly wide range of cases.2 I think the most plausible answer is something in-between. …
    Found 4 days, 2 hours ago on Good Thoughts
  25. 372235.386001
    Our adversarial system of international relations poses substantial risks of violent catastrophe and impedes morally urgent initiatives and reform collaborations. The domestic politics of our more advanced societies provide guidance toward a better world, governed by just rules which ensure that basic human needs are met, inequalities are constrained, and weapons and wealth are marginalized as tools for influencing political and judicial outcomes. Impartial administration, adjudication, and enforcement of just rules requires a strong normative expectation on officials and citizens to fully subordinate their personal and national loyalties to their shared commitment to the just and fair functioning of the global order. As we have fought (and often defeated) nepotism within states, we must fight nepotism in behalf of states to overcome humanity’s great common challenges. To moralize international relations, states can plausibly begin with reforming the world economy toward ending severe poverty, thereby building the trust and respect needed for more difficult reforms.
    Found 4 days, 7 hours ago on Thomas Pogge's site
  26. 374222.386008
    The relation between sensing/cognition and mental disorders (āfāt al-dhihn) receives special attention in Avicenna’s writings on psychology and medicine. Avicenna identifies two ways of diagnosing mental disorders: one way is in relation to the function of the senses, while the other is in relation to the internal faculties. A psychological phenomenon commonly exhibited in such disorders is the experience of hallucinatory content, that is, registering perceptible content that does not exist to what assumed to be the correspond to an existing object in external reality. In this chapter, I set out to investigate the cognitive process underlying the experience of hallucinatory content, and to show the significant roles that compositive imagination plays in creating and imposing this content upon sensory experience.
    Found 4 days, 7 hours ago on Ahmed Alwishah's site
  27. 398741.386015
    Ted Sider famously argues for the universality of composition on the grounds that: If composition is not universal, then one can find a continuous series of cases from a case of no composition to a case of composition. …
    Found 4 days, 14 hours ago on Alexander Pruss's Blog
  28. 437648.386021
    Current political affairs offer interesting, even if dramatic, instances of applied political philosophy problems. Reading the news today, I found at least two such problems, both related to populist politics – one concerns Meloni and Italy, and the other concerns Trump and the U.S. …
    Found 5 days, 1 hour ago on The Archimedean Point
  29. 437649.386027
    Drug overdose deaths have more than doubled in America in the past 10 years, mainly due to the appearance of Fentanyl and other synthetic opioids. These drugs combine incredible ease of manufacture with potency in tiny amounts and dangerousness (the tiniest miscalculation in dosage makes them deadly). …
    Found 5 days, 1 hour ago on The Philosopher's Beard
  30. 437650.386033
    To Advocate "Don't Do Anything Risky!" is Risky Passivity norms and status quo bias Many people endorse norms that presumptively oppose action in the face of uncertainty. They unreflectively assume that passivity is the “cautious”, risk-averse option. …
    Found 5 days, 1 hour ago on Good Thoughts